Some of my friends and students must be tired of hearing this: “We do philology because
we have to. We do philosophy because we want to.” Those of us who love to do
Buddhist philosophy of the past have no choice but to do Buddhist philology as
well. Because, in my view, there can be no (textual) Wortphilologie without (contentual-contextual) Sachphilologie, and no Sachphilologie
without Wortphilologie, philology
must necessarily be an academic discipline that deals with both and one that seeks
to gain a diachronic and synchronic views of the texts and ideas. As such
philology is inextricably linked his history. A philologist is necessarily also
a historian of ideas. But what kind of a historian are we talking about? This
reminds me of the typology of historian proposed once by Edward Conze.
According to him, there are three types of historian: scientific, humanistic,
and transcendental. I quote (Conze 1967 = 2000: 28): “The first studies a
butterfly after killing it and fixing it with a pin into a glass case, where it
lies quite still and can leisurely be inspected from all angles. The second
lets it fly in the sun, and looks wonderingly at its pretty ways. The third
assures us that a man will know a butterfly only if he becomes one.” Using the
idea of intellectual deconstruction (i.e. rigs
pas gzhig pa) and physical destruction
(i.e. gnyen pos gzhig pa), I
would like to propose that what a historian of ideas usually seeks to do is to pursue
analytical dissection but not a physical one, and hence one actually does not
have to kill the butterfly. Or, after having analytically dissected the object
of study with one’s prajñā, one can, out
of one’s karuṇā, assemble all the
parts and put them back to its original form.
(Personal blog of Dorji Wangchuk (Kuliśeśvara) for philosophical reflection, speculation, and deliberation)
Monday, October 19, 2015
Buddhist Philosophy on actus reus and mens rea?
Here is a random thought that just popped up in my mind. It is said that the expressions actus reus and mens rea were developed in
English Law and were derived from the principle stated by Edward Coke,
namely, actus non facit reum nisi
mens sit rea (“an act does not make a person guilty unless (their)
mind is also guilty”). Hence the general test of guilt is said to be one that
requires proof of fault, culpability or blameworthiness both in
thought and action. I know that we have been repeatedly warned of the pitfalls
and perils of comparing Eastern and Western ideas. Nonetheless, I cannot help
thinking of the Buddhist idea that the wholesomeness, unwholesomeness, or
neutrality of an action is always determined by the wholesomeness, unwholesomeness,
or neutrality of intention or motivation. It also seems worth bearing
in mind that an action or deed (which, by the way, must be by definition
volitional) can only then be considered karmically efficacious or
potent if it has been committed with the right gzhi, bsam pa, sbyor ba, and mthar thug. Thus one speaks of byas la bsags pa’i las (“committed-and-accumulated karmic
deed”) and byas la ma bsags pa’i las (“committed-but-not-accumulated
karmic deed”). There is thus the possibility (also in Buddhism) for making
a difference between, for example, “murder” and “manslaughter.” Suppose I
have accumulated tons of negative karmic deeds but what would happen
to my karmic loads if I were to suddenly attain Arhatship and pass
way into the restless nirvāṇa? (Note
that negative karmic deeds need not necessary bar one to attain Arhatship.)
That would be a bad luck for my karma! In German, one would say: “Karma hat eben Pech gehabt!”
Subscribe to:
Posts (Atom)