The term “deontology” is said to be derived from
Greek deon “obligation, duty” and logia “discourse.” Deontology
(or deontological ethics) is said to be “the normative ethical position that
judges the morality of an action based on the action’s adherence to a rule or
rules. It is sometimes described as ‘duty’ or ‘obligation’ or ‘rule’-based
ethics, because rules ‘bind you to your duty.’ Deontological ethics is commonly
contrasted to consequentialism, virtue ethics, and pragmatic ethics. In this
terminology action is more important than the consequences” (Wikipedia).
The question for me is whether we can speak of “Buddhist deontology.” I feel
that we can speak of “Buddhist deontology,” particularly in the Mahāyāna
context, insofar as Buddhism accepts that the rightness or wrongness (or
perhaps better, in the Buddhist context, the wholesomeness or unwholesomeness
or neutrality) of one’s verbal and physical conduct is determined by the
wholesome, unwholesome, or neutral character or nature of the behavior itself
rather than the outcomes of the conduct. Two related arguments seem to support
the fact in Buddhism even if the action carried out of a compassionate motive
or intention turns out to harm other people, it would nonetheless be considered
wholesome.
We are told by some that Kantanism (or Immanuel
Kant’s theory of ethics) is deontological for at least two different reasons:
First, Kant has argued that to act in the morally right way, people must act
from duty (deon). Second, Kant has argued that it was not the
consequences of actions that make them right or wrong but the motives of the
person who carries out the action.
Kant’s first argument that to act in the morally
right way, people must act from duty (deon) is said to be based on the
argument that the highest good must be both good in itself and good without
qualification. Does this argument make any sense from the perspective of
Buddhist axiology? Not being sure if Kant’s position has been represented
accurately, it is difficult to say. What does seem questionable is the idea of
“duty” in Buddhism. Does it exist in Buddhism and what does it mean? On the one
hand, prima facie, at least, we might get an impression that in Buddhism no one
is obliged to do anything for anyone, and thus the idea of duty in the sense of
obligation simply makes no sense. Such an impression is perhaps created by the
fact that Buddhism proposes karmic mechanism and presupposes what Srinivasan
has once called Heilsprivatismus (“Salvific Privatism”), which
means that each person is responsible for his or her this-worldly or
other-worldly mundane destiny and also for one’s soteriological destiny. Whatever
one does, one does so out of self-responsibility and not on account of one’s
obligation or responsibility towards others. What about one’s duty towards
one’s parents, family, and the like? One may perhaps state that this is nothing
specifically Buddhistic but rather a societal norm accepted by the society at
large. One might thus argue that duty is akin to a penalty and it robs one’s
personal freedom to choose and decide. Thus the very word “duty” sounds
somewhat contrarious to the Buddhist pattern of thinking. On the other hand, it
should be emphasized that Buddhist axiology does prescribe
ethical-moral-ascetical commitment and responsibility. Although “duty” or
“obligation” may be synonymous to “commitment,” the latter term seems more
appropriate in the Buddhist context. The basic idea here is that although one
is not obliged to do anything for anyone, one does have the complete freedom to
commit oneself to do something or not to something. But once one has taken a
commitment upon oneself, one is usually bound by one’s commitment. Even here,
one take full responsibility for keeping or breaking one’s commitment. This
distinction, in my view, seems crucial. For a person who has not committed
himself or herself to refrain from killing, abstaining from killing a human
being out of maliciousness is not a duty. For a person who has committed
himself or herself to refrain from killing, abstaining from killing a human
being out of maliciousness is a duty.
Kant’s idea of “good in itself and good without
qualification” seems to be reconcilable with the Buddhist idea of certain
mental factors/associates (caitta: sems las byung ba) that are by nature
wholesome (ngo bo nyid kyis dge ba).
By the way, its opposite, those that are by nature unwholesome (ngo bo nyid kyis mi dge ba), too, is
possible in Buddhism. If to (re)formulate Kant’s argument in Abhidharmic terms,
it would be thus: “To act in the ethically-morally right way, people must act
with wholesome mental factors (dge ba’i sems byung).” Better still: “Any
action carried out with wholesome mental factors (dge ba’i sems byung) is ethically/morally right.”
Kant’s second reason, in my view, seems to
be ad sensum same as the first argument and thus both
arguments seem readily acceptable from a Buddhist perspective. This is also the
reason why I think Buddhist axiology proposes deontological ethics.
What would a Buddhist philosopher think of
Kant’s categorical imperative? “Act only according to that maxim by which you
can also will that it would become a universal law.” I think it would be found
laudable and endorsable. I have a feeling that the Mahāyānic values crystalized
in the six kinds of perfections (pāramitā: pha rol tu phyin pa) imply
categorical imperative.
Does Buddhist axiology propose “moral
absolutism,” according to which certain actions are absolutely right or wrong,
regardless of the intentions behind them as well as the consequences? From a
Buddhist perspective, it would seem that the very idea of “moral absolutism”
(i.e. if what I read is what it says) seems to be based on the presupposition
(or rather on the misconception) that there is an intention-free action.
Action, deed, or exertion in Buddhism must be volitional. Action is not a
motivation-free or intention-free motion. The rustling of dry leaves in the
wind is not an action. One may, however, conceive of a Buddhist version of
“moral absolutism,” according to which certain mental actions are absolutely
right or wrong, regardless of their consequences. In other words, a unwholesome
mental action is always and absolutely wrong, and a wholesome mental action is
always and absolutely right.
On the one hand, the so-called “Divine Command
Theory,” according to which “an action is right if God has decreed that it is
right” would be deprecated by a Buddhist philosopher as utterly nonsensical
because it would be tantamount to stating that “an action is right if the Son
of a Barren Woman (or Rabbit’s Horn) has decreed that it is right.” On the
other hand, Buddhist sources classify misdeeds that are considered by nature
unwholesome and thus by nature reproachable (prakṛtisāvadya: rang bzhin gyi
kha na ma tho ba) and those that are reproachable in virtue of prohibition
or decree (pratikṣepaṇasāvadya, also rendered into Tibetan as bcas
pa’i kha na ma tho ba). The question here is to find something to be
“reproachable” by whom? The answer is: a wise person (e.g. the Buddha). A
fool’s judgment of something as “reproachable” or “irreproachable” is not
valid.